資料類別: | 2007年12月大學英語六級考試最新預測試卷及答案 |
資料格式: | WORD格式 |
資料來源: | 考試吧(Exam8.com) |
資料下載: | 點擊這里下載 |
Section I Use of English
Part A
Directions: Read the following text. Choose the best word(s) for each numbered blank and mark A,B,C or D on ANSWER SHEET 1.(10 points)
The basic function of money is the enable buying to be separated from selling, thus permitting trade to take place without the socalled double coincidence of barter. If a person has something to sell and wants something else 1 return, it is not necessary to search for someone able and 2to make the desired exchange of items. The person can sell the 3 item for general purchasing power—that is, “money”—to anyone who wants to buy it and then use the proceeds to buy the desired item from anyone who wants to sell it.
The importance of this function of money is 4 illustrated by the experience of Germany just after World War Ⅱ, 5 paper money was 6 largely useless because, despite inflationary conditions, price controls were effectively 7 by the American, French, and British armies of occupation. People had to8 to barter or to inefficient money substitutes. The result was to cut total output of the economy in half. The German “economic miracle” just after 1948 reflected partly a currency reform by the occupation authorities, 9 some economists hold that it stemmed primarily from the German government’s 10 of all price controls, 11 permitting a money economy to 12 a barter economy.
13 of the act of sale from the act of purchase 14 the existence of something that will be generally accepted in payment—this is the “15 of exchange” function of money. But there must also be something that can serve as a 16 abode of purchasing power, in which the seller holds the proceeds in the interim 17 the first sale and the 18 purchase, or from which the buyer can 19the general purchasing power with which to pay 20 what is bought. This is the “asset” function of money.
1. [A] on [B] in [C] by [D] for
2. [A] capable [B] likely [C] desirable [D] willing
3. [A] excess [B] extra [C] surplus [D] ample
4. [A] dramatically [B] urgently [C] faithfully[D] incidentally
5. [A] when [B] before [C] since [D] until
6. [A] developed [B] reserved [C] rendered [D] imagined
7. [A] encouraged [B] enlarged [C] endured [D] enforced
8. [A] conform [B] resort [C] commit [D] gear
9. [A] and [B] but [C] therefore [D] however
10. [A] deprivation [B] stimulation[C] elimination[D] restriction
11. [A] thereby [B] therefore [C] then [D] while
12. [A] alternate [B] establish [C] substitute[D] replace
13. [A] Introduction [B] Specification[C] Representation [D] Separation
14. [A] assumes [B] requires [C] focuses [D] undertakes
15. [A] medium [B] function [C] role [D] nature
16. [A] fashionable [B] favorable [C] temporary [D] token
17. [A] both [B] for [C] between [D] after
18. [A] consequent [B] relevant [C] inadequate[D] subsequent
19. [A] execute [B] extract [C] exceed [D] exchange
20. [A] for [B] off [C] back [D] in
Section Ⅱ Reading Comprehension
Part A
Directions:
Read the following four texts. Answer the questions below each text by choosing A, B, C or D. Mark your answers on ANSWER SHEET 1. (40 points)
Text 1
Two related paradoxes also emerge from the same basic conception of the aesthetic experience. The first was given extended consideration by Hegel, who argued roughly as follows: our sensuous attention and that gives to the work of art its peculiar individuality. Because it addresses itself to our sensory appreciation, the work of art is essentially concrete, to be understood by an act of perception rather than by a process of discursive thought.
At the same time, our understanding of the work of art is in part intellectual; we seek in it a conceptual content, which it presents to us in the form of an idea. One purpose of critical interpretation is to expound this idea in discursive form—to give the equivalent of the content of the work of art in another, nonsensuous idiom. But criticism can never succeed in this task, for, by separating the content from the particular form, it abolishes its individuality. The content presented then ceases to be the exact content of that work of art. In losing its individuality, the content loses its aesthetic reality; it thus ceases to be a reason for attending to the particular work and that first attracted our critical attention. It cannot be this that we saw in the original work and that explained its power over us.
For this content, displayed in the discursive idiom of the critical intellect, is no more than a husk, a discarded relic of a meaning that eluded us in the act of seizing it. If the content is to be the true object of aesthetic interest, it must remain wedded to its individuality: it cannot be detached from its “sensuous embodiment” without being detached from itself. Content is, therefore, inseparable from form and form in turn inseparable from content. (It is the form that it is only by virtue of the content that it embodies.)
Hegel’s argument is the archetype of many, all aimed at showing that it is both necessary to distinguish form from content and also impossible to do so. This paradox may be resolved by rejecting either of its premises, but, as with Kant’s antinomy, neither premise seems dispensable. To suppose that content and form are inseparable is, in effect, to dismiss both ideas as illusory, since no two works of art can then share either a content or a form-the form being definitive of each work’s individuality.
In this case, no one could ever justify his interest in a work of art by reference to its meaning. The intensity of aesthetic interest becomes a puzzling, and ultimately inexplicable, feature of our mental life. If, on the other hand, we insist that content and form are separable, we shall never be able to find, through a study of content, the reason for attending to the particular work of art that intrigues us. Every work of art stands proxy for its paraphrase. An impassable gap then opens between aesthetic experience and its ground, and the claim that aesthetic experience is intrinsically valuable is thrown in doubt.
21. Hegel argued that .
。跘] it is our sensuous appreciation that gives peculiar individuality to the work of art
。跙] it is the content of the work of art that holds our attention
。跜] the work of art cannot be understood without a process of logical thinking
[D] the form of the work of art is what our sensuous appreciation concentrates on
22. It can be inferred from this passage that .
。跘] the paradox that it is both necessary to distinguish form content and also impossible to do so cannot be resolved by rejecting its premises
[B] both content and form of the work of art are illusory
。跜] the content and form of the work of art are separable
。跠] aesthetic experience is not intrinsically valuable
23. Which of the following is NOT what Hegel believed?
。跘] The content and form of the work of art cannot be separated from each other.
。跙] The content of the work of art is always the true object of aesthetic interest.
。跜] The content presented without any individuality is not the content of the work of art.
[D] The content understood by means of a process of discursive thought is no more than a husk.
24. Premises that are related to each other seems to be dispensable because .
。跘] Kant thinks they are indispensable
[B] either of them can resolve the paradox
。跜] the premises are separated
。跠] the premises can account for the theory
25. This passage is mainly about .
。跘] the sensuous appreciation of art
。跙] the basic conception of the aesthetic experience
。跜] how to appreciate the work of art
[D] the relationship between form and content of the work of art
更多信息請訪問:考試吧四六級欄目
北京 | 天津 | 上海 | 江蘇 | 山東 |
安徽 | 浙江 | 江西 | 福建 | 深圳 |
廣東 | 河北 | 湖南 | 廣西 | 河南 |
海南 | 湖北 | 四川 | 重慶 | 云南 |
貴州 | 西藏 | 新疆 | 陜西 | 山西 |
寧夏 | 甘肅 | 青海 | 遼寧 | 吉林 |
黑龍江 | 內(nèi)蒙古 |